Friday, October 28, 2016

Originalists against Trump and the concept of the principled stand

by Craig L. Jackson Professor of Law, Thurgood Marshall School of Law, Texas Southern University, Houston, Texas

[originalistsagainsttrump.wordpress.com]

A long list of conservative lawyers, mostly law professors, but many practitioners as well, recently published a signed manifesto explaining why they, proponents of the constitutional interpretive theory of originalism, will not be voting for Donald Trump this election season. These people are mostly intellectuals and will have little if any influence on the voting preference of persons in the typical demographics of Trump nation—white working class and frustrated, as well as, presumably the alt-right. More likely than not people who would take note, or even be aware of their stand are either people like me, too liberal to even say the words “vote Trump”, conservatives who likely already have made up their minds not to vote for Trump, or maybe the Mike Pence types—mainstream conservatives who are supporting Trump while pinching their noses in hopes that he can be handled if he becomes president. While the Originalists may influence some of these latter folks, it is hard for me to grasp how the publication of “Originalists against Trump” could have any real impact.

So why do it? My best guess—Principle.

Originalists are proponents of the view that the Constitution should be interpreted according to the framers’ intent, or (if you are a Scalia originalist) how the document was originally understood. Whether one’s favor is in the sparse notes of the Philadelphia Convention in 1787, or more generally prefer how the document was viewed when it was ratified by the people, which was the view of the late Antonin Scalia, if you are an originalist, you have had debates over how to apply that original intent or understanding to modern problems. It is by nature a conservative philosophy of interpretation. And inasmuch as the country was founded by conservatives who were admired by the eighteenth century conservative British political theorist Edmund Burke, and has essentially a conservative history, heck if you are an originalist, you have nothing to lose. But the rest of us do if we view the document as one based on classical liberal theory capable of application beyond the narrow confines of 18th century post-colonial America. Perhaps Justice William Brennan said it best when he described originalism in a lecture he delivered at Georgetown University in 1985:

[upholding] constitutional claims only if they were within the specific contemplation of the Framers in effect establish a presumption of resolving textual ambiguities against the claims of constitutional right.


Brennan went on to say:


[t]his is a choice no less political than any other; it expresses antipathy to claims of the minority to rights against the majority. Those who would restrict claims of right to the values of 1789 …turn a blind eye to social progress and eschew adaptation of overarching principles to changes of social circumstance.


Originalists claim that original meaning is the closest thing to pure unadulterated interpretation--the original bargain struck when the Constitution went into effect. As such it is devoid of the personal political preference of less conservative interpreters of the document. Fair enough, and inasmuch as this is not a blog about the virtues or non-virtues of originalism, I will just leave it right here, for now.

Some would argue, I presume, that these Originalists, as conservatives, are taking a risk in the sense that if their opposition to the Trump candidacy takes hold, or they are otherwise influential as part of an uprising among conservatives against the Trump candidacy, Trump will lose and Clinton will win. From the standpoint of my perception that the professional lives of these individuals are taken up by the Constitution, the Supreme Court, and the decisions of that body, this is a risk. This is because the current court is aging at key points. Anthony Kennedy, Ruth Bader Ginsburg, and Stephen Breyer may chose to retire soon, leaving key vacancies. A conservative president would replace Breyer and Ginsburg with conservatives and Kennedy, a swing voter, with a more reliable conservative and change the Court’s philosophy for at least a generation. With the help of a Democratic Senate (which at this writing is a possibility) a liberal president would replace Kennedy with a reliable liberal on a variety of issues. So, as their manifesto acknowledges, a Clinton presidency will appoint anyone but originalists to the Supreme Court. A “Clinton Court” will very likely be like the “Roosevelt Court” in reference to the fact that the last Roosevelt appointee to the Court (William O. Douglas) remained on the Court until the Ford administration, a period of 36 years. And the Roosevelt appointees were instrumental in changing constitutional jurisprudence in ways that are still vital today.

With so much at stake from their conservative viewpoint, why take this position? Originalists against Trump offer their own constitutional rationale for opposing a Trump presidency. And it is rooted in principle, and not in the ideological makeup of the Court. From their manifesto:


• The President must take care that the laws be faithfully executed; he admires dictators as above the law.
• The President must serve as Commander in Chief, enforcing rules for the government and regulation of the land and naval forces; he praises armed repression and makes light of the laws of war.
• The President must hold a public trust on behalf of all Americans; he courts those who would deny to others the equal protection of the laws.
• The President must preserve, protect, and defend the Constitution; he has treated the legal system as a tool for arbitrary and discriminatory ends, especially against those who criticize him or his policies.


The Originalists have chosen fitness for presidential leadership as the lead arguments against a Trump presidency knowing full well that the likely outcome is a generation of Court decisions that do not reflect the interpretive method of Originalism. Some conservatives have expressed the hope that the Senate will remain Republican to serve as a barrier to the appointment of liberals to the Court. But all this really guarantees is the appointment of Merrick Garland types, moderates with slight conservative tendencies. Certainly not the conservative leaning individuals that Trump has indicated that he will appoint.

To Trump’s promise to appoint conservatives to the Court, the Originalists say that they do not believe him:


We also understand the argument that Trump will nominate qualified judicial candidates who will themselves be committed to the Constitution and the rule of law. Notwithstanding those he has already named, we do not trust him to do so.


But even that swipe at the Republican candidate is laced with additional opprobrium:


More importantly, we do not trust him to respect constitutional limits in the rest of his conduct in office, of which judicial nominations are only one part.


I get angry when I read dissents by the late Antonin Scalia, who was a godfather of sorts to the Originalists signing on to this manifesto. I get angry when I read articles or briefs by some of the signers of the manifesto as well. But it is a professional anger based on my sincere belief that Originalism is just a façade to justify incorporating conservative values that Originalists already have into the Constitution, claiming that such conservative outcomes were predetermined by the document. So when I say that the framers were conservative, I mean it in the sense that their world view was limited by the values, of the time—the racism of slavery, the patriarchy, the mercantilist economies, the rugged individualism of an agrarian nation—none of which exist today (I know that is a broad statement, and I can defend it, but perhaps that should be the subject of another blog). But the broad principles of liberty embodied in that Constitution apply today more universally than anticipated at the time of its drafting. Originalists do not have a satisfying answer to how one takes these values as limited to the meaning of the time and applies them to the diverse society of our present time. Nonetheless, in a real sense, they are putting it all on the line—including the influence legal scholars and lawyers will generally have in an administration close to their ideological preference—out of fear of the nature of government and society in a Donald Trump lead America.

Liberal constitutional scholars should take note and consider the same situation on different sides—a moderate, flawed conservative running for president against liberal of questionable integrity, reckless ideas, and a willingness to place his/her interests above that of the nation,. Knowing the fate of the ideology of the Court would be lost for a generation if the moderately conservative, though flawed candidate won, would liberals write a manifesto and take the stand taken by these Originalists?

The Originalists end their manifesto with the following:


We are under no illusions about the choices posed by this election—or about whether Hillary Clinton, were she elected, would be any friend to originalism. Yet our country’s commitment to its Constitution is not so fragile that it can be undone by a single administration or a single court. Originalism has faced setbacks before; it has recovered. Whoever wins in November, it will do so again.


And finally:


Originalism is a commitment to the Constitution, not to any one political party. And not every person who professes support for originalism is therefore prepared to be President. We happen to see Trump as uniquely unsuited to the office, and we will not be voting for him.


If they are influential, or if their preferred outcome—that Donald Trump not be elected—comes to pass, and assuming a cooperative Senate (an unstated assumption in the manifesto) well, that’s pretty much it for originalism for a generation and pretty much it for their influence of the Originalists on legal policy and judicial appointments for a good while.

It’s a principled and gutsy call.




Originalists against Trump and the concept of the principled stand

by Craig L. Jackson Professor of Law, Thurgood Marshall School of Law, Texas Southern University, Houston, Texas



A long list of conservative lawyers, mostly law professors, but many practitioners as well, recently published a signed manifesto explaining why they, proponents of the constitutional interpretive theory of originalism, will not be voting for Donald Trump this election season. These people are mostly intellectuals and will have little if any influence on the voting preference of persons in the typical demographics of Trump nation—white working class and frustrated, as well as, presumably the alt-right. More likely than not people who would take note, or even be aware of their stand are either people like me, too liberal to even say the words “vote Trump”, conservatives who likely already have made up their minds not to vote for Trump, or maybe the Mike Pence types—mainstream conservatives who are supporting Trump while pinching their noses in hopes that he can be handled if he becomes president. While the Originalists may influence some of these latter folks, it is hard for me to grasp how the publication of “Originalists against Trump” could have any real impact.

So why do it? My best guess—Principle.

Originalists are proponents of the view that the Constitution should be interpreted according to the framers’ intent, or (if you are a Scalia originalist) how the document was originally understood. Whether one’s favor is in the sparse notes of the Philadelphia Convention in 1787, or more generally prefer how the document was viewed when it was ratified by the people, which was the view of the late Antonin Scalia, if you are an originalist, you have had debates over how to apply that original intent or understanding to modern problems. It is by nature a conservative philosophy of interpretation. And inasmuch as the country was founded by conservatives who were admired by the eighteenth century conservative British political theorist Edmund Burke, and has essentially a conservative history, heck if you are an originalist, you have nothing to lose. But the rest of us do if we view the document as one based on classical liberal theory capable of application beyond the narrow confines of 18th century post-colonial America. Perhaps Justice William Brennan said it best when he described originalism in a lecture he delivered at Georgetown University in 1985:

[upholding] constitutional claims only if they were within the specific contemplation of the Framers in effect establish a presumption of resolving textual ambiguities against the claims of constitutional right.


Brennan went on to say:


[t]his is a choice no less political than any other; it expresses antipathy to claims of the minority to rights against the majority. Those who would restrict claims of right to the values of 1789 …turn a blind eye to social progress and eschew adaptation of overarching principles to changes of social circumstance.


Originalists claim that original meaning is the closest thing to pure unadulterated interpretation--the original bargain struck when the Constitution went into effect. As such it is devoid of the personal political preference of less conservative interpreters of the document. Fair enough, and inasmuch as this is not a blog about the virtues or non-virtues of originalism, I will just leave it right here, for now.

Some would argue, I presume, that these Originalists, as conservatives, are taking a risk in the sense that if their opposition to the Trump candidacy takes hold, or they are otherwise influential as part of an uprising among conservatives against the Trump candidacy, Trump will lose and Clinton will win. From the standpoint of my perception that the professional lives of these individuals are taken up by the Constitution, the Supreme Court, and the decisions of that body, this is a risk. This is because the current court is aging at key points. Anthony Kennedy, Ruth Bader Ginsburg, and Stephen Breyer may chose to retire soon, leaving key vacancies. A conservative president would replace Breyer and Ginsburg with conservatives and Kennedy, a swing voter, with a more reliable conservative and change the Court’s philosophy for at least a generation. With the help of a Democratic Senate (which at this writing is a possibility) a liberal president would replace Kennedy with a reliable liberal on a variety of issues. So, as their manifesto acknowledges, a Clinton presidency will appoint anyone but originalists to the Supreme Court. A “Clinton Court” will very likely be like the “Roosevelt Court” in reference to the fact that the last Roosevelt appointee to the Court (William O. Douglas) remained on the Court until the Ford administration, a period of 36 years. And the Roosevelt appointees were instrumental in changing constitutional jurisprudence in ways that are still vital today.

With so much at stake from their conservative viewpoint, why take this position? Originalists against Trump offer their own constitutional rationale for opposing a Trump presidency. And it is rooted in principle, and not in the ideological makeup of the Court. From their manifesto:


• The President must take care that the laws be faithfully executed; he admires dictators as above the law.
• The President must serve as Commander in Chief, enforcing rules for the government and regulation of the land and naval forces; he praises armed repression and makes light of the laws of war.
• The President must hold a public trust on behalf of all Americans; he courts those who would deny to others the equal protection of the laws.
• The President must preserve, protect, and defend the Constitution; he has treated the legal system as a tool for arbitrary and discriminatory ends, especially against those who criticize him or his policies.


The Originalists have chosen fitness for presidential leadership as the lead arguments against a Trump presidency knowing full well that the likely outcome is a generation of Court decisions that do not reflect the interpretive method of Originalism. Some conservatives have expressed the hope that the Senate will remain Republican to serve as a barrier to the appointment of liberals to the Court. But all this really guarantees is the appointment of Merrick Garland types, moderates with slight conservative tendencies. Certainly not the conservative leaning individuals that Trump has indicated that he will appoint.

To Trump’s promise to appoint conservatives to the Court, the Originalists say that they do not believe him:


We also understand the argument that Trump will nominate qualified judicial candidates who will themselves be committed to the Constitution and the rule of law. Notwithstanding those he has already named, we do not trust him to do so.


But even that swipe at the Republican candidate is laced with additional opprobrium:


More importantly, we do not trust him to respect constitutional limits in the rest of his conduct in office, of which judicial nominations are only one part.


I get angry when I read dissents by the late Antonin Scalia, who was a godfather of sorts to the Originalists signing on to this manifesto. I get angry when I read articles or briefs by some of the signers of the manifesto as well. But it is a professional anger based on my sincere belief that Originalism is just a façade to justify incorporating conservative values that Originalists already have into the Constitution, claiming that such conservative outcomes were predetermined by the document. So when I say that the framers were conservative, I mean it in the sense that their world view was limited by the values, of the time—the racism of slavery, the patriarchy, the mercantilist economies, the rugged individualism of an agrarian nation—none of which exist today (I know that is a broad statement, and I can defend it, but perhaps that should be the subject of another blog). But the broad principles of liberty embodied in that Constitution apply today more universally than anticipated at the time of its drafting. Originalists do not have a satisfying answer to how one takes these values as limited to the meaning of the time and applies them to the diverse society of our present time. Nonetheless, in a real sense, they are putting it all on the line—including the influence legal scholars and lawyers will generally have in an administration close to their ideological preference—out of fear of the nature of government and society in a Donald Trump lead America.

Liberal constitutional scholars should take note and consider the same situation on different sides—a moderate, flawed conservative running for president against liberal of questionable integrity, reckless ideas, and a willingness to place his/her interests above that of the nation,. Knowing the fate of the ideology of the Court would be lost for a generation if the moderately conservative, though flawed candidate won, would liberals write a manifesto and take the stand taken by these Originalists?

The Originalists end their manifesto with the following:


We are under no illusions about the choices posed by this election—or about whether Hillary Clinton, were she elected, would be any friend to originalism. Yet our country’s commitment to its Constitution is not so fragile that it can be undone by a single administration or a single court. Originalism has faced setbacks before; it has recovered. Whoever wins in November, it will do so again.


And finally:


Originalism is a commitment to the Constitution, not to any one political party. And not every person who professes support for originalism is therefore prepared to be President. We happen to see Trump as uniquely unsuited to the office, and we will not be voting for him.


If they are influential, or if their preferred outcome—that Donald Trump not be elected—comes to pass, and assuming a cooperative Senate (an unstated assumption in the manifesto) well, that’s pretty much it for originalism for a generation and pretty much it for their influence of the Originalists on legal policy and judicial appointments for a good while.

It’s a principled and gutsy call.




Friday, July 29, 2016

The 5th Circuit to Texas—Senate Bill 14’s voter ID provisions violates the Voting Rights Act of 1965—it's discriminatory. Get it this time?

Craig L. Jackson, Professor of Law Thurgood Marshall School of Law at Texas Southern University


As did many of the hot cases from last term, my prediction for the next hot Supreme Court case has Texas written all over it though it will probably not make it to the Supreme Court until the 2017 term. Veasey v. Abbott is about voter ID in Texas, and it addresses the question of whether what remains of the Voting Rights Act of 1965 after one of its pre-clearance provisions were gutted by 2013’s Shelby v. Holder decision can be effectively used to protect voting rights. In July, the 5th Circuit Court of Appeals said yes in an opinion written by Judge Haynes and joined by eight other circuit court judges. At least to a degree. The decision was a partial victory for solid and protected voting rights. And it elicited an angry principal dissent written by Judge Edith Jones which was joined by four other judges.

A little background is in order. Voting rights are protected by the Fifteenth Amendment to the Constitution which states:

The right of citizens of the United States to vote shall not be denied or abridged by the United States or by any state on account of race, color or previous condition of servitude.

The amendment also gives Congress the authority to pass appropriate legislation to protect that franchise from both outright denial or interference. The Voting Rights Act of 1965 (VRA) is the principle enforcement legislation of the Fifteenth Amendment. When the Supreme Court ruled that the provisions of the VRA that required states (like Texas) with a particularly ominous history of voting discrimination and their governmental units to submit election changes to the Department of Justice or the federal courts in Washington DC for pre-clearance approval before the changes could be implemented was unconstitutional, the author of the opinion, Chief Justice John Roberts tried to ameliorate the effect of the decision by suggesting that challenges to election changes could be made through Section 2 of the Act. Section 2 offers a litigation option for plaintiffs with standing to challenge election law changes on the basis that they violate the provision:

a) No voting qualification or prerequisite to voting or standard, practice, or procedure shall be imposed or applied by any State or political subdivision in a manner which results in a denial or abridgement of the right of any citizen of the United States to vote on account of race or color, or in contravention of the guarantees set forth in section 1973b(f)(2) [language minorities] of this title...


Unlike pre-clearance which was automatic and operated as a provisional stay on election law changes until approved by either the DC federal courts or the Justice Department, Section 2 is not automatic , works only insofar as there are willing plaintiffs willing to take on the expense of litigation, and is effective in preventing changes from going into effect only insofar as such a challenge can survive the arcane procedural requirements in place, to obtain a restraining order or injunction against implementation. No, it is not analogous to pre-clearance, not nearly as effective, the quality of the policing of election rule changes is questionable, and it was created simply as an option for challengers not satisfied with pre-clearance results. It should be noted that the VRA does offer at section 3 a procedure in which a federal court (as in any federal court—not limited to the federal courts in the District of Columbia) retains jurisdiction to pre-clear (or to accept Justice Department pre-clearance findings) any election change by any political unit found to have intentionally discriminated in its election laws, an issue in this section 2 case. If the district court on remand finds intentional discrimination and that finding holds up on appeal, Texas may have backed itself back into pre-clearance, but this time under section 3.

The voter ID requirement is in a provision of the Texas law known as Senate Bill 14 (SB 14). The bill requires, as is the current vogue among many states nationally, voters to present picture identification as a pre-requisite for voting in elections. Last year the 5th Circuit, ruling under Section 2, held the Texas law discriminatory in effect on minorities. Texas requested and got a rehearing before the entire fifteen person court and in a 9-6 decision the entire court found that the provision had a discriminatory effect on African Americans and Hispanics. As for intent, the district court had earlier found both intent and effect discrimination. While Judges Dennis and Costa would have accepted the district court’s intent holding, a plurality of seven of the 5th Circuit agreed that not all of the evidence of intent was solid and remanded the case back to Judge Nelva Gonzales Ramos for further review on the issue of intent discrimination. However, a majority of the court did believe that the record contained some evidence of intent of the Texas Legislature to discriminate. Among the evidence that the majority thought promising includes the fact that forms of ID more frequently held by minorities in Texas (government employment ID) do not qualify under the new law, and the fact that there is a paltry number of voter fraud claims in Texas and the Legislature’s decision to fast track that legislation over other important and impending bills. To the majority, this maneuver seemed dubious at best. It should be noted, however, that the Supreme Court has ruled that fraud prevention, whatever the attendant statistics in a particular state, is a legitimate reason to enact a voter ID law.

Now, about photo ID. A comment under a friend’s enthusiastic post of the court decision on her Facebook page asked the question, paraphrased here, amounting to “what’s the big deal about requiring identification?” It is a reasonable question. Texas voters will recall as recently as the 2012 election that one could walk up to the polling officer, show a voter registration card which does not have a photograph of the holder (or in the alternative, a drivers license, or student or government employee ID, each of which do have photographs of the holder, or a utility bill, a bank statement, a paycheck, a government document showing the voter’s name and address, or mail addressed to the voter from a government agency), receive a voting ticket and proceed to the closest vacant voting machine. Since then, after the passage of SB 14, I have arrived at the polling officer’s desk with my drivers’ license out. It seems natural, so much so that I barely take note of it when I vote—after all I have to provide ID for a number of less important tasks—I have to give ID just to pick up will call tickets at an Isley Brothers concert. So what is the big deal?

The “big deal” has to do with access to ID and the effect on the poor, who are disproportionately black and Hispanic in this state. In essence, the Texas Legislature cut back on the kinds of acceptable ID, preferring some photo ID to other kinds of photo ID that were acceptable under the old law (such as the student and government employee ID), and cut out any other kinds of non photographic proof of an individual’s identity. While undoubtedly most African Americans and Hispanics can get necessary ID, those that cannot because of their poverty matter. And they matter not just in a caring kind of way. In an election in Texas, local or statewide, a few thousand disqualified African American votes here, and a few thousand disqualified Hispanic votes there, and you may have a different outcome.

Obtaining a photo ID costs money. Presently, photographic proof of identity, social security number, US citizenship or lawful residence, and Texas residence is required. But if a person is not a driver, what are the options? A military ID will suffice, and if one is a gun owner with a license to carry a concealed handgun (which has picture ID), that’ll work in the Great State! A US citizenship certificate will suffice as well to get you to a voting machine. Finally there is the Election Identification Card (EIC) for non vets who do not drive and prefer not to carry concealed weapons on their person. All of these include a photo and none of these forms are acceptable if expired more than 60 days at the time of voting. Student IDs and government employee IDs are out (which typically include a photo of the holder), as are any kind of non-photographic, though official, or creditable, identification.

Pretty detailed stuff here. But no more so, I guess, than the instructions to a 1040 form. But wait, pretty soon we are in Schedule d capital gains and losses territory kind of complex!

The majority described the requirements for getting an ID in the opinion:

To receive an EIC, DPS rules require a registered voter to present either: (A) one form of primary ID, (B) two forms of secondary ID, or (C) one form of secondary ID and two pieces of supporting identification. 37 TEX. ADMIN. CODE § 15.182(1). Thus, any application for an EIC requires either one Texas driver’s license or personal identification card that has been expired for less than two years, or one of the following documents, accompanied by two forms of supporting identification: (1) an original or certified copy of a birth certificate from the appropriate state agency; (2) an original or certified copy of a United States Department of State Certification of Birth for a U.S. citizen born abroad; (3) U.S. citizenship or naturalization papers without a photo; or (4) an original or certified copy of a court order containing the person’s name and date of birth and indicating an official change of name and/or gender.


In other words, to get an ID one must have—an ID. The notion of having to get an ID to get and ID may sound funny but there are costs involved. For persons in poverty, the EIC is the best bet. That is because the Legislature, after passing SB 14, passed new legislation waiving the fees for the EIC. But there are still the fees for the forms of ID needed to get the EIC.

District Court Judge Ramos called this state of affairs a poll tax, a requirement from the old days and found unconstitutional in the 60s requiring persons to pay to vote if they did not meet other requirements, but the 5th Circuit ruled against her on that point. Following Judge Ramos opinion finding discrimination, the Legislature passed a bill in the 2015 session waiving costs for birth certificates requested for purposes of getting an EIC. That leaves US Department of State, citizenship or naturalization papers, any out of state birth certificate, or court order uncovered by any cost saving measure. Of course these are the kinds of documents you would normally expect people would normally keep handy. But do they, and should a consequence of not being so careful be denial of the franchise?

One expert made the following point at the district court hearing:

[U]nreliable and irregular wage work and other income . . . affect the cost of taking the time to locate and bring the requisite papers and identity cards, travel to a processing site, wait through the assessment, and get photo identifications. This is because most job opportunities do not include paid sick or other paid leave; taking off from work means lost income. Employed low-income Texans not already in possession of such documents will struggle to afford income loss from the unpaid time needed to get photo identification.


Based on this and other evidence, the majority noted that Judge Ramos determined “that the poor are less likely to avail themselves of services that require ID, such as obtaining credit and other financial services. They are also less likely to own vehicles and are therefore more likely to rely on public transportation. As a result, the poor are less likely to have a driver’s license and face obstacles in obtaining photo identification. Id. Even obtaining an EIC poses an obstacle—the district court credited evidence that hundreds of thousands of voters face round-trip travel times of 90 minutes or more to the nearest location issuing EICs. Of eligible voters without access to a vehicle, a large percentage faced trips of three hours or more to obtain an EIC.”

Simply stated, there are hidden costs under the present law that could prove more burdensome on poor people. Other states, recognizing this effect, have instituted indigency exceptions to the ID requirement. When given the opportunity to include such an exception to the photo ID requirement (which was included in the version of the bill passed by the Texas Senate), the Texas House declined. Linking voting to other forms of ID more available to minority voters such as student IDs, state government employee IDs, and federal IDs—IDs that are disproportionately held by African–Americans and Hispanics was passed on as well (admittedly not linked to indigency, but the Legislature’s decision to decline these forms remains inexplicable nonetheless). This and other evidence offered lead to the district court’s conclusion that members of the Texas Legislature were well aware that the rules would have a disproportionate effect on poor Texans. The district court took note of the fact that an Indiana voter ID program found constitutional by the Supreme Court contained ameliorative provisions declined by the Legislature. Yet the bill was passed anyway. And the district court found discrimination.

The disproportionate effect on the poor, disproportionately minority in Texas, appears to have been established, even if to middle class observers the inconveniences seem trivial. And even though there is no final opinion on the issue of intent to discriminate, the disproportionate impact appears well established. But not to the judges filing principal dissent in this case.

Judge Edith Jones penned the principal dissent in this case which was joined by four other members of the 5th Circuit minority in this case. Judge Jones’ dissent has several analytical points, but a few bear mentioning in this blog. Initially I believe that the dissenters were miffed that the majority dismissed the lower court’s intent finding, identified what looked to the majority as intent evidence, and then basically wrote the lower court’s opinion for it when it remanded with instructions. The dissent may have a point there, though I am not aware of any ethical or procedural rule violated.

The dissenters also note the lack of any proof that a significant number of minority voters were disenfranchised by the law. In fact, only a few individuals were identified in the litigation as having had difficulty voting or were declined access to the polls, and several of them are plaintiffs in the case. This is a curious critique of the majority opinion in that the district court, and the majority on the disparate impact portion of the ruling, appears to have established that the voting rights of a significant number of African American and Hispanic voters had been harmed by the voter ID law. The data indicated the number of members of both groups did not have necessary documentation to get adequate ID to vote, and experts testified as to costs and the obstacles posed by those costs associated with accumulating the documentation. To the dissent this was irrelevant—no proof of vote denial means no proof of vote denial. The dissent seems to argue that affected voters may be able to overcome the obstacles associated with the law and if so, they should not be counted as evidence of denial.

The majority and the concurrence point out that the term abridgement accompanies the term denial in section 2 and that abridgement of the right to vote refers to any reduction or diminution of the vote including all aspects of the process of voting necessary to make the vote effective. So under section 2 both denial and abridgement are prohibited. And the evidence appears to establish that the new law made it more difficult to qualify for voting to the point that vote denial is a likely consequence.

Yet the dissent had doubts about the significance of the numbers. The fact is that the vast majority of African American and Hispanic voters have the needed ID to vote. However statistical analysis relied on by the district court found significant percentage swings in the likelihood of having SB 14 identification materials when Anglo citizens are compared to African American and Hispanic voters (305% and 195% respectively). These are statistics and reflect relatively small percentages of the minority populations in the state. Nonetheless, these are potentially election affecting numbers. Yet the principal dissent would have the litigants address evidence of whether or not these citizens were able to cure their ID problems in time for the next election to count as actual vote denial.

Hence the main problem with voting rights protection. Supporters of strong voting rights protection understand what happens when the quality of the voting experience, including registration and casting, is hampered by new rules—the results of elections are affected. So supporters are confident enough with evidence of abridgement that they will seek to access the remedies in the VRA in advance of an election despite the fact that denial is impossible to prove at this point. Those critical of strong voting rights protection measures for whatever reason (textualism, originalism, federalism), need to see evidence of actual vote denial. But one cannot be denied a vote until one presents oneself to the polls on election day, and then it’s too late if the importance of voting is to have one’s say in electing government under which one lives. This is why pre-clearance was so important under the portion of the law gutted by the Supreme Court in Shelby County.

Remedy

The majority remanded the matter back to the district court mindful of the 2016 elections which include the election of the President of the United States. Judge Ramos of the district court was instructed to develop interim measures, mindful of what appropriate purposes the Texas Legislature had when it passed SB 14, and also mindful of the disparate impact discrimination finding on the part of both the district court and the 5th Circuit majority. Those voters unaffected by the voter ID law will have to use ID next November. The impact on those affected by the voter ID law, i.e. those having difficulty getting proper documentation, will be the subject of the remedy. After the election Judge Ramos may address the discriminatory intent issue and may hold hearings on the matter.

A date before the Supreme Court is a sure thing. Since SCOTUS has already upheld voter ID laws with less restrictive rules than Texas, like those of Indiana, the Texas case will simply define the extent that states may go in requiring ID when the Supreme Court rules in a couple of years. You can expect that states determined to have voter ID laws for whatever reason, will push the boundaries of any Court decision in the future.

This issue, like this case, is not over.

Thursday, July 14, 2016

The Interesting Case of the Notorious RBG (Ruth Bader Ginsburg)

Craig L. Jackson, Professor of Law, Thurgood Marshall School of Law

By now the story is familiar: A well regarded and progressive Supreme Court Justice speaks her mind about a candidate for the Presidency of the United States, in three publications, receives responsible criticism from credible sources(the editorial boards of both the New York Times and the Washington Post), some less than credible criticism (the candidate's criticism with an ageist insinuation about the justice's intellectual faculties), and finally an apology, a week before the candidate will likely be officially nominated as his party's candidate for office.

Here are some links (copy and paste):

AP Interview: Ginsburg doesn't want to envision a Trump win
bigstory.ap.org/article/0da3a641190742669cc0d01b90cd57fa/ap-interview-ginsburg-reflects-big-cases-scalias-death">


New York Times: Ruth Bader Ginsburg: No Fan of Donald Trump; Critiques Latest Term
www.nytimes.com/2016/07/11/us/politics/ruth-bader-ginsburg-no-fan-of-donald-trump-critiques-latest-term.html">

CNN: Ruth Bader Ginsburg Doesn't want to Imagine a Trump Presidency
www.cnn.com/2016/07/08/politics/ruth-bader-ginsburg-donald-trump/index.html?utm_source=feedburner&utm_medium=feed&utm_campaign=Feed%3A+rss%2Fcnn_latest+(RSS%3A+CNN+-+Most+Recent)">">


New York Times Editorial: Donald Trump Is Right About Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg
www.nytimes.com/2016/07/13/opinion/donald-trump-is-right-about-justice-ruth-bader-ginsburg.html?_r=0">

Washington Post Editorial: Justice Ginsburg’s inappropriate comments on Donald Trump
www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/justice-ginsburgs-inappropriate-comments-on-donald-trump/2016/07/12/981df404-4862-11e6-bdb9-701687974517_story.html">

Donald Trump Tweet:
twitter.com/realDonaldTrump/status/753090242203283457">

Washington Post: In bashing Donald Trump, some say Ruth Bader Ginsburg just crossed a very important line
www.washingtonpost.com/news/the-fix/wp/2016/07/11/in-bashing-donald-trump-some-say-ruth-bader-ginsburg-just-crossed-a-very-important-line/">


And here are some other links regarding other Supreme Court Justices:

The New Yorker: Justice O'Connor Regrets
www.newyorker.com/news/daily-comment/justice-oconnor-regrets">


Bush vs. Gore Has Personal Angle For Some Supreme Court Justices
www.wsj.com/articles/SB976572470116168521">


New York Times: Scalia Angrily Defends his Duck Hunt with Dick Cheney
www.wsj.com/articles/SB976572470116168521">


Cheney v. United States District Court for the District of Columbia
scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=3663421335325675419&q=cheney+v.+usdc+district+of+columbia&hl=en&as_sdt=6,44&as_vis=1">

The last four links are of course about behavior by Justices Sandra Day O'Connor and Antonin Scalia that raised eyebrows. O'Connor's expression of regret when at a party on election night in 2000 when it looked like Al Gore was going to win the presidential election is a classic cocktail party conversation piece and was originally reported by Jeffrey Toobin and recounted in his New Yorker article about regrets about the wisdom of the Court in taking the Bush v. Gore case, which decided the election that she was distressed about at that election night party.

Other interesting comments and associations that also raised eyebrows was reported by the Wall Street Journal shortly after the Bush v. Gore oral arguments. And finally Justice Scalia's infamous hunting trip with then Vice President Dick Cheney is recounted by the New York Times, a trip that took place while the Court was considering Cheney v. United States District Court for the District of Columbia, the case about Cheney's secret energy task force meetings and the effort to force disclosure of the attendees. Finally, his memorandum, published as a court document, describing his reasons for not recusing himself, including the fact that the Cheney case deals with Cheney in his official, and not personal, capacity.

O'Connor like Ginsburg, expressed displeasure with regard to a presidential election. But O'Connor's expression was private, overheard by Toobin's source, and not intended for public consumption. And seriously, does anyone believe that she would be overjoyed by a Gore victory?

Ginsburg, on the other hand participated in three interviews with major media outlets. Her language was detailed and the product of deliberation. Indeed she is one of the most accomplished wordsmiths in the United States, and at least in the English language. And so I concur with the New York Times and Washington Post--public discourse can do without partisan statements by Supreme Court justices. I prefer my progressive heroes and issues free of distracting blemishes, and this is just that. Avoidance of evident bias, the obligation to employ and to maintain the appearance of judicial temperament is an important part of the game we play when we talk about the Supreme Court's legitimacy. Of course we know, that the really controversial cases before the Court are political. Though occasionally a Justice will vote against his/her own political or social mores, I do not believe that this happens often.

But on the other hand, all she did was state the obvious. Ruth Bader Ginsburg, the Notorious One, is well known to be a political liberal as her background as the Thurgood Marshall of feminist litigation and her numerous opinions, concurrences, and dissents will attest. What she said was not news. The fact that she said it was.

Antonin Scalia's behavior was perhaps different from Ginsburg's. He openly associated with a litigant in a case he was to hear, though the case was about Vice President Dick Cheney in his official capacity. But it was not a private show of displeasure, or a detached dissing. It was hanging out. That is a different degree to my mind, and recusal should have been more seriously considered by the justice, even though the case involved official actions with no personal stake of the Vice President involved, with the exception perhaps, of his political prestige. And political prestige is a big thing for the Washington power crowd. Damn near personal!

As to whether Ginsburg would need to recuse herself in a case involving a President Trump--its doubtful. As far as official capacity cases, the Scalia precedent would apply. However, another Bush v. Gore case (God forbid), would be another matter.

Well, anyway, she apologized this morning. Contrition shows character, something woefully missing in today's political discourse.


New York Times: Ruth Bader Ginsburg expresses regret for criticizing Trump
www.nytimes.com/2016/07/15/us/politics/ruth-bader-ginsburg-donald-trump.html">









The Interesting Case of the Notorious RBG (Ruth Bader Ginsburg)

Craig L. Jackson, Professor of Law, Thurgood Marshall School of Law

By now the story is familiar: A well regarded and progressive Supreme Court Justice speaks her mind about a candidate for the Presidency of the United States, in three publications, receives responsible criticism from credible sources(the editorial boards of both the New York Times and the Washington Post), some less than credible criticism (the candidate's criticism with an ageist insinuation about the justice's intellectual faculties), and finally an apology, a week before the candidate will likely be officially nominated as his party's candidate for office.

Here are some links (copy and paste):

AP Interview: Ginsburg doesn't want to envision a Trump win
bigstory.ap.org/article/0da3a641190742669cc0d01b90cd57fa/ap-interview-ginsburg-reflects-big-cases-scalias-death">


New York Times: Ruth Bader Ginsburg: No Fan of Donald Trump; Critiques Latest Term
www.nytimes.com/2016/07/11/us/politics/ruth-bader-ginsburg-no-fan-of-donald-trump-critiques-latest-term.html">

CNN: Ruth Bader Ginsburg Doesn't want to Imagine a Trump Presidency
www.cnn.com/2016/07/08/politics/ruth-bader-ginsburg-donald-trump/index.html?utm_source=feedburner&utm_medium=feed&utm_campaign=Feed%3A+rss%2Fcnn_latest+(RSS%3A+CNN+-+Most+Recent)">">


New York Times Editorial: Donald Trump Is Right About Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg
www.nytimes.com/2016/07/13/opinion/donald-trump-is-right-about-justice-ruth-bader-ginsburg.html?_r=0">

Washington Post Editorial: Justice Ginsburg’s inappropriate comments on Donald Trump
www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/justice-ginsburgs-inappropriate-comments-on-donald-trump/2016/07/12/981df404-4862-11e6-bdb9-701687974517_story.html">

Donald Trump Tweet:
twitter.com/realDonaldTrump/status/753090242203283457">

Washington Post: In bashing Donald Trump, some say Ruth Bader Ginsburg just crossed a very important line
www.washingtonpost.com/news/the-fix/wp/2016/07/11/in-bashing-donald-trump-some-say-ruth-bader-ginsburg-just-crossed-a-very-important-line/">


And here are some other links regarding other Supreme Court Justices:

The New Yorker: Justice O'Connor Regrets
www.newyorker.com/news/daily-comment/justice-oconnor-regrets">


Bush vs. Gore Has Personal Angle For Some Supreme Court Justices
www.wsj.com/articles/SB976572470116168521">


New York Times: Scalia Angrily Defends his Duck Hunt with Dick Cheney
www.wsj.com/articles/SB976572470116168521">


Cheney v. United States District Court for the District of Columbia
scholar.google.com/scholar_case?case=3663421335325675419&q=cheney+v.+usdc+district+of+columbia&hl=en&as_sdt=6,44&as_vis=1">

The last four links are of course about behavior by Justices Sandra Day O'Connor and Antonin Scalia that raised eyebrows. O'Connor's expression of regret when at a party on election night in 2000 when it looked like Al Gore was going to win the presidential election is a classic cocktail party conversation piece and was originally reported by Jeffrey Toobin and recounted in his New Yorker article about regrets about the wisdom of the Court in taking the Bush v. Gore case, which decided the election that she was distressed about at that election night party.

Other interesting comments and associations that also raised eyebrows were reported by the Wall Street Journal shortly after the Bush v. Gore oral arguments. And finally Justice Scalia's infamous hunting trip with then Vice President Dick Cheney is recounted by the New York Times, a trip that took place while the Court was considering Cheney v. United States District Court for the District of Columbia, the case about Cheney's secret energy task force meetings and the effort to force disclosure of the attendees. Finally, his memorandum, published as a court document, describing his reasons for not recusing himself, including the fact that the Cheney case deals with Cheney in his official, and not personal, capacity.

O'Connor like Ginsburg, expressed displeasure with regard to a presidential election. But O'Connor's expression was private, overheard by Toobin's source, and not intended for public consumption. And seriously, does anyone believe that she would be overjoyed by a Gore victory?

Ginsburg, on the other hand participated in three interviews with major media outlets. Her language was detailed and the product of deliberation. Indeed she is one of the most accomplished wordsmiths in the United States, and at least in the English language. And so I concur with the New York Times and Washington Post--public discourse can do without partisan statements by Supreme Court justices. I prefer my progressive heroes and issues free of distracting blemishes, and this is just that. Avoidance of evident bias, the obligation to employ and to maintain the appearance of judicial temperament is an important part of the game we play when we talk about the Supreme Court's legitimacy. Of course we know, that the really controversial cases before the Court are political. Though occasionally a Justice will vote against his/her own political or social mores, I do not believe that this happens often.

But on the other hand, all she did was state the obvious. Ruth Bader Ginsburg, the Notorious One, is well known to be a political liberal as her background as the Thurgood Marshall of feminist litigation and her numerous opinions, concurrences, and dissents will attest. What she said was not news. The fact that she said it was.

Antonin Scalia's behavior was perhaps different from Ginsburg's. He openly associated with a litigant in a case he was to hear, though the case was about Vice President Dick Cheney in his official capacity. But it was not a private show of displeasure, or a detached dissing. It was hanging out. That is a different degree to my mind, and recusal should have been more seriously considered by the justice, even though the case involved official actions with no personal stake of the Vice President involved, with the exception perhaps, of his political prestige. And political prestige is a big thing for the Washington power crowd. Damn near personal!

As to whether Ginsburg would need to recuse herself in a case involving a President Trump--it's doubtful. As far as official capacity cases, the Scalia precedent would apply. However, another Bush v. Gore case (God forbid), would be another matter.

Well, anyway, she apologized this morning. Contrition shows character, something woefully missing in today's political discourse.


New York Times: Ruth Bader Ginsburg expresses regret for criticizing Trump
www.nytimes.com/2016/07/15/us/politics/ruth-bader-ginsburg-donald-trump.html">








Saturday, July 9, 2016

Fisher Blog: Why Justice Alito’s dissent in Fisher v. The University of Texas is so important. (Hint: it’s about the argument weaknesses that it exposes, on both sides!) Part II


This year’s decision is a return performance of litigation that went to the Court in 2013. The Court remanded the case for more explanation of UT’s reasons for the two tiered diversity plan and a demonstration of whether it was narrowly tailored to reach the goals that it had set for diversity. I am posting a two part blog this time. In Part I, I discussed the Alito dissent’s main argument critiquing the majority decision in favor of the University of Texas admissions program and how Justice Alito’s demand that UT explain its diversity goals with precision would eventually force UT to name a number, which would make the program a quota, which is unconstitutional.

I post this second installment on the occasion of my high school mass reunion which I attended last weekend (Hebert High School Beaumont Texas 1922-1982). I have included my high school in this essay because I am writing about the dissent, and so much in Alito’s dissent is about my high school, and high schools like it, its legacy, what people think its legacy is, and hypocrisies on both sides.

From part I:

The decision is now history. Texas has a rather convoluted history with academic affirmative action, with its modern beginnings in the 5th Circuit opinion of Hopwood v. Texas, on to a double tiered diversity admissions process, with one using race, as allowed by the Supreme Court, and another process utilizing the fact that Texas high schools, like most states with large urban areas (certainly New York, California, Florida, and Illinois meet this description), the high schools are racially identifiable. By taking the top ten percent of the graduating classes from all high schools, you guarantee some diversity.

The Supreme Court decided that the University of Texas had established compelling reasons for using race along with the top ten percent plan in putting together its entering classes, and that the methodology was narrowly tailored to achieve the levels of academic diversity needed for the school’s educational mission.


Inner City Blues

UT’s argued that it needed to employ both admissions methods because the top ten percent plan did not do enough to establish a critical mass of underrepresented minority students across the majors and courses offered by the University. But then there is question of what critical mass is, and the method of reaching that critical mass at UT that Justice Alito focuses on and his critique of the method that is worth at least a sympathetic look by this progressive.

Back to my class reunion in Beaumont, Texas. Twenty years ago I wrote a law review article titled "Hebert High School and the Brown Aftermath: Good Intentions and Troubled Policy", 21 T. Marshall L. Rev. 45 (1996). The article describes in much more detail what I will attempt to describe in the next few paragraphs.

In the piece I critiqued school desegregation policy during the late 60s, 70,s and 80s. I attended Hebert in the 1960s and 70s and was aware of the desegregation movement and the policy employed to improve the educational opportunities of children of color under the rubric of the Brown decision. I understood the implications of the policy of integration at all costs, and I did not like it. I was one of those children of color whose educational opportunities were in need of improving because I and my classmates with whom I hung out this weekend were enrolled at an inner city black high school. In my view the term inner city black high school has become an epithet meaning substandard and underachieving, violent, and generally distasteful. It is an unfair characterization but one that seems to stick since it became a part of the vocabulary of school desegregation policy in the 60s and 70s.

Our reunion this week is what is called a mass reunion, where the survivors of the earliest classes able to attend (in our case this year, a 98 year old graduate of the class of ’34) celebrate our legacy with the alumni of the last classes in our school’s history. Our school, which opened in 1922, was closed in 1982 for the purposes of desegregation, an interesting term to describe a closure that occurred 28 years after school segregation under the mandate state law had been outlawed by the Supreme Court. So it is fair to say that at least those of us who attended Hebert after 1965, when the Brown decision was finally implemented in Beaumont made the choice out of our own free will, and not under a legal mandate.

I have worked in education, at least at the professional school level for about 26 years now, and I have thought about these issues since I was in high school. In many ways our school was a typical single race minority school of its time, and in many ways, it was different. Though I have not done a scientific study to tie these assertions down, I do believe that the achievement levels that we have attained are not what one thinks of when one thinks of inner city schools. And yes, our school was underfunded by racist’s allocation policies implemented by what was then a racist majority white school board. But there were the intangibles, the quality of teaching, the spirit, the notion of community that made our school great. The individual achievements of my fellow “Panthers” are nothing short of amazing. Hell, I am talking about it 43 years after graduation. And what examiners not familiar with the minority schools of that era will find upon embarking on serious research into those institutions is that our kind of “amazing” existed at minority schools across the nation. Perhaps many, if not every major or midsized city could claim an exceptional black or Hispanic school. We had excellent and well credentialed teachers, a tradition of academic excellence, and a school spirit that made us want to achieve. All we needed was a little more money. But that was impossible as long as the white high schools in the district were getting more than their share of tax dollars for their facilities. I believe to this day that a litigation strategy focused on resource allocation equality, under Equal Protection precedent, would have produced far better results for schools today than the “integrate at all cost” policies that were employed that turned out failed outcomes. This is because the institutions pursuing the implementation of Brown decided early on that any majority minority school was, by virtue of this racial characteristic alone, a violation of Brown, a decision dealing with state mandated segregation. So a strategy of eliminating majority minority schools was pursued instead of ensuring that all schools had adequate funding for academic programs. In Houston, this resulted in the recently renamed Jefferson Davis and Robert E. Lee high schools being majority minority as minority students were zoned to these schools, leading to the predictable mass exodus of white students. Professor Derrick Bell called for a reexamination of this strategy in his groundbreaking 1976 article "Serving two Masters: Integration Ideals and Client Interests in School Desegregation Litigation":


The espousal of educational improvement as the appropriate goal of school desegregation efforts is out of phase with the current state of the law. Largely through the efforts of civil rights lawyers, most courts have come to construe Brown v. Board of Education as mandating “equal educational opportunities” through school desegregation plans aimed at achieving racial balance, whether or not those plans will improve the education received by the children affected.


Bell went on to explain in a later article his interest convergence theory. Ending state mandated segregation may have served the purposes of white elites and others separated from black student populations in 1954, but by the time school desegregation came to mean massive bussing to achieve racial balance, most of those whites had decided that their interest were not served and sought more separation from black student populations through white flight. None of this contributed to quality black education. Likely, an opportunity for quality black and minority education had been squandered because of the strategy of desegregation of that time.


Bad Words

The big issue in Fisher is the fact that UT undergraduate admissions operated under what is the Top Ten Percent plan. In its original form, students graduating in the top ten percent of their high school’s class are offered admissions to UT Austin. It is a color blind plan on its face created in response to a woefully incompetently written opinion by the 5th Circuit in the 1996 Hopwood v. Texas case which ruled that the University of Texas School of Law’s admissions policies violated the Equal Protection Clause because of the law school's use of race as a factor in admissions decisions, a decision effectively overruling the Supreme Court’s Bakke decision—something lower courts are not supposed to do. Though not a national decision, it would be the law in Texas and a few other states in the 5th Circuit for the next several years. The Texas Legislature responded to the ruling by enacting the Top Ten Percent plan for undergraduate students (though no alternative for graduate or professional programs in the state was offered). In order for diversity to work, the plan relied on the one race nature of a significant number of Texas high schools (some would say segregated, though, as I have explained, I believe the term in this context is legally imprecise). These schools are either what I’ll call HMHS (historically minority high schools), newly created neighborhood minority schools, or formerly white schools (like Davis and Lee) that became minority over time due to white flight. They exists as a result of several factors including white flight, and decisions by federal courts, including the Supreme Court, releasing school districts from federal court desegregation orders where re-segregation occurred as a result in neighborhood changes.

After Grutter v. Bollinger made clear that the diversity standard for the use of race as a factor remained constitutional, UT returned to using race as a factor, while maintaining the ten percent policy. This meant that UT had two plans in place to reach its preferred diversity goals.

Justice Alito is correct to criticize UT’s reasons behind its use of race, though it would be nice to see this passion from the good justice in other areas addressing social and economic racism in his jurisprudence. UT had a course coverage problem under the ten percent plan (not enough underrepresented minority students enrolled in the full selection of courses and majors at one of the nation’s best public schools), and it said it had an academic quality problem under that plan as well. Alito characterized UT’s argument as arguing that the minority students drawn from the ten percent plan “tend to come from poor, disadvantaged families, and the University would prefer a system that gives it substantial leeway to seek broad diversity within groups of underrepresented minorities”. According to UT’s brief in the first Fisher case, UT needed intra-racial diversity that would include the “African-American or Hispanic child of successful professionals in Dallas”. In the first trial in the first case, the transcript has UT representatives testifying that “although the percentage plan certainly helps with minority admissions, by and large, the—minorities who are admitted tend to come from segregated, racially-identifiable schools.”

The real problem at the University of Texas is simply the paltry numbers of underrepresented minorities in a school of over 50,000 students. The most readily available enrollment data from UT’s website (at least what I could find) is from 1984, 7 years after I arrived for law school and 4 years after I graduated. Out of a total enrollment of 47,973, the black enrollment figures were 1582, or 3.29% (graduate and undergraduate combined). Current statistics have black enrollment at just under 3.9% (graduate and undergraduate combined). That’s about 1987 black students, .671 percentage points from where it was almost 40 years ago. As it seeks to remedy that circumstance, one gets the impression that it chose to focus on the need to diversify certain majors and classes that were undersubscribed by underrepresented minorities, and on beefing up the admissions credentials of those groups. To do so, it represented its method as going after intra-racial diversity, and in doing that, it used language, at least in the first case, that disparaged students from “racially identifiable” schools.

This is a hard call on the part of the University. It needed to provide a reason for using race on top of the ten percent policy, and it picked its language from the old vocabulary of the school desegregation movement—racially identifiable, read racially identifiable minority schools, means less capable students, means, more capable students are from schools that were not racially identifiable minority schools (whether or not those schools were racially identifiable white schools). Reading the University’s use of language reminded me of a comment made to me by a black friend who was a colleague of mine in a city wide black youth organization who attended a racially identifiable white school. Our youth group, Top Teens of Beaumont, gave out awards to members whose class rank was at the top of their respective schools. I got my award as did other kids from majority black schools. My friend who attended a “white” school suggested that the awards should have been more evenly distributed among students attending white schools (something to the effect, “I should have gotten one of those awards even if I did not finish in the top percentile at my school—it was a white school after all.” Seriously, he said that.)

I am pretty sure that everybody at my reunion has been disparaged at some point in our high school and post high school lives (before we could establish ourselves in true adulthood) in some way because of the racial identity of Hebert High School. This list of alums include an alum who is a retired Yale trained mathematician, political leaders, Harvard and UT trained medical doctors and medical school professors, and other medical professionals, a retired Naval Academy graduate fighter pilot, high ranking officers of the United States Military, school teachers, hard working blue collar employees, lawyers, college professors, skilled workers and supervisors in the local industries, excellent parents, tax paying citizens, at least one FBI agent, plant and corporate managers, and at least one UT Law trained law professor as far as I know. The list could continue.

And the University of Texas did not have to make that argument. In its brief in the first case, UT noted the limitations of the top ten percent plan because “even assuming such plans are race-neutral, they may preclude the university from conducting the individualized assessments necessary to assemble a student body that is not just racially diverse, but diverse along all the qualities valued by the university” quoting the Grutter majority opinion. This means that what UT calls its holistic admissions approach, it could consider the race of a black math genius who did not make it to the top decile, or an Hispanic cellist who excels in the high school orchestra but did not finish in the top ten percent. Or that it could supplement its top ten diversity with high achieving minority applicants who may not have made it in under the top ten plan.

However, in support of this in the first case, UT went into that old territory of language designed for the function of “salvation” from racially identifiable minority schools. In describing the urban educational realities of modern day America UT argued in its 2012 brief:


[t]hat segregation produces clusters of overwhelmingly majority-minority schools—largely confined to particular geographic areas of the State—that tend to produce large numbers of minority admits under the top 10% law. But that clustering also means that the top 10% law systematically hinders UT’s efforts to assemble a class that is broadly diverse, and academically excellent, across the board—including within groups of underrepresented minorities.


Let’s be honest here. Like I mentioned earlier, UT’s black numbers are roughly what they were when I showed up there in a large Afro and jeans with holes in them 39 years ago. So in two generations, with all of UT’s resources and with the state literally leaking black academic talent like a sieve to out of state private and state schools, UT has not significantly increased its black enrollment numbers. But UT’s defense of its affirmative action program in the first case was in essence that it cannot produce an academically excellent program while taking in all those minority top percentage students. The fact of the matter is that it has blown the last 40 years, most of which under Bakke’s “ race as a consideration” affirmative action admission standard, by failing to solve the problem.

Considering the spate of litigation this term involving the state of Texas, the UT people were motivated by far kinder instincts than were behind either the abortion or immigration cases from the Great State heard by SCOTUS this term where the state government was a litigant. But this is UT, where perhaps more enlightened voices prevail, and the Office of the Attorney General is not involved in this litigation, and taking up this challenge is to the credit of UT’s administration, Board of Regents and legal team. However, UT’s position in 2012 was not complimentary. If you measure quality by where a student is at a given moment (like right out of one of these inner city schools) the characterization is very likely true because the difference between the academic facilities for learning at some schools and others is too often huge, and not one of the students in either type of school had anything to do with where they wound up. But one has to consider effort, desire, and intangibles that the Texas state legislature, in one of its occasional decent legislative moments, deemed important for its flagship university to embrace.

Nonetheless, that math genius that I mentioned earlier, may not make it to the top ten percent at a highly competitive high school, but UT wants that student and it wants an affirmative action plan that allows them to offer admission to that kid. Why? “Because that kid is smart and we have a compelling interest in admitting the smartest students we can under Grutter”. But instead, UT’s argument in the 2012 brief was that it needs the math nerd “because the inner city kids are not very good.”

Alito is clever and seizes on that use of language to write like a racially sensitive liberal:


“[u]ltimately, UT’s intraracial diversity rationale relies on the baseless assumption that there is something wrong with African-American and Hispanic students admitted through the Top Ten Percent Plan, because they are “from the lower-performing, racially identifiable schools.”


Justice Alito also noted:


And UT’s assumptions appear to be based on the pernicious stereotype that the African-Americans and Hispanics admitted through the Top Ten Percent Plan only got in because they did not have to compete against very many whites and Asian-Americans.


But the progressive world shuddered when the late Justice Scalia said during oral argument in Fisher last December, “[t]here are – there are those who contend that it does not benefit African Americans to --to get them into the University of Texas where they do not do well, as opposed to having them go to a less--advanced school, a less – a slower-track school where they do well.” This statement was met with outrage, but when compared with UT’s own arguments from the first case, it’s hard to argue that the two statements together are terribly different and hard not to argue that they both amount to an unfortunate description of black and other underrepresented minority students.

And the arguments were not necessary, as UT recognized in its brief for the second case.

UT’s earlier argument, largely walked back and or abandoned in 2015-16, under-appreciates the hard work that people put into making these inner city school’s work. These schools are populated by students who had nothing to do with their educational circumstances but who will be looked at funny by fellow students, instructors, and apparently by admissions officers when they go to college. I know because people looked at us funny when affirmative action was just beginning in the 70s. This kind of vision of top students from the inner city is not comfortable—it’s stifling, it sucks, and it is counterproductive, fully capable of producing the very results predicted, possibly in large part because of the pressure placed on these kids, and on us when we were young.

Like I said, UT walked that argument back this year with much more ameliorative language while discussing the influential Harvard University diversity admissions plan:


To illustrate how the “critical criteria” in achieving the educational benefits of diversity “are often individual qualities or experience not dependent upon race but sometimes associated with it,” the Harvard plan gave the example of two different African-American applicants—“A, the child of a successful black physician in an academic community with promise of superior academic performance, and B, a black who grew up in an inner-city ghetto of semiliterate parents whose academic achievement was lower but who had demonstrated energy and leadership as well as an apparently abiding interest in black power.” The plan recognized that each of these applicants would add to student body diversity in their own unique ways, and that the university’s diversity interest would be furthered by both.


Though this new language speaks to a more holistic view of being a minority kid seeking an education in this country, it still relies on the assumption that the inner city kid as a remedial project. The new brief does not consider the kid from one of those exceptional minority schools that I have been describing that defies all expectations by scoring higher than she should and performing at a level not expected because she attended a racially identifiable minority school, maybe like the kids to whom I give scholarship money in honor of my parents, educators in those inner city schools of Beaumont Texas. Or maybe like me, an affirmative action student at Rice, but a normal admit if I had chosen UT 43 years ago out of my inner city high school.

What UT has apparently learned since the first case is that positive descriptions of students that it professes to want to admit is crucial to a good admissions policy because it needs to send the message that the students are really wanted. It needs to act and speak in a positive manner so that its minority admissions numbers over the next two generations will actually rise and not stay stagnant. I hope that it has also learned that the imprecise use of language having to do with a previous generation’s desegregation battles should not color racial admissions policy at one of the nation’s largest and best public schools. What I also hope it learned is about the hard work of students, teachers, and administrators in places like the old Hebert, and similar present day schools—hard work that does not always show up well in raw statistics and data generated from the most general of cumulative samples of schools of a particular category.

Ok, we’ve gotten the decision we wanted. Now it is time to go to work at the Forty Acres.

Hook ‘Em Horns!




.

Thursday, July 7, 2016

Fisher Blog: Why Justice Alito’s dissent in Fisher v. The University of Texas is so important. (Hint: it's about the argument weaknesses that it exposes, on both sides!) Part I

Craig L. Jackson, Professor of Law Thurgood Marshall School of Law, Texas Southern University
I have begun writing this after mulling over this idea all week since the decision came on in late June. Today, I am gathering my thoughts after re-reading the dissent and starting my introduction. In a few minutes I will shower, shave, and hit the road to Beaumont, Texas to my high school mass reunion (Hebert High School 1922-1982). I include this itinerary because I am writing about the dissent, and so much in Alito’s dissent is about my high school, its legacy, what people think its legacy is, and hypocrisies on both sides.

The decision is now history. Texas has a rather convoluted history with academic affirmative action, with its modern beginnings in the 5th Circuit opinion of Hopwood v. Texas, on to a double tiered diversity admissions process, with one using race, as allowed by the Supreme Court, and another process utilizing the fact that Texas high schools, like most states with large urban areas (certainly New York, California, Florida, and Illinois meet this description), the high schools are racially identifiable. By taking the top ten percent of the graduating classes from all high schools, you guarantee some diversity.

The Supreme Court decided that the University of Texas had established compelling reasons for using race along with the top ten percent plan in putting together its entering classes, and that the methodology was narrowly tailored to achieve the levels of academic diversity needed for the school’s educational mission.

I am writing a two part blog today. In Part II I critique language used by UT in its 2012 brief about the quality of minority students from minority schools, the top ten percenters. As I demonstrate upon posting, it is language that should never have been used to describe these kids (or me as I was one of those kids once) but unfortunately it is language that has been staple in the old desegregation litigation and activism of a previous generation.

In this first instalment of the "Fisher Blog" I write about the Alito dissent because we are going to hear about this dissent for years to come. This term saw two big culture war cases before the Court. In addition to this case, there is Whole Women’s Health v. Hellerstedt the abortion rights decision. The cases were decided after the death of Justice Antonin Scalia. Though neither of the vote tallies indicate that a Scalia vote would have changed the outcome (Fisher, 4-3 (Kagan abstaining)--a Scalia vote would have tied the outcome resulting in an affirmance of the pro UT ruling in the 5th Circuit); Whole Women’s Health, 5-3), Alito’s dissent amounts to about as spirited a critique of the pro affirmative action opinion as one will get post Scalia and his points will be discussed for years.

The Alito Dissent

Like most dissents on either side of the ideological divide, Alito’s includes the requisite recriminations about the motives of the majority, accusations of lack of candor on the part of the Court’s opinion, insinuations about the competence of the majority—though absent here are attacks on the personal character of the majority, a regular feature of dissents of the late Antonin Scalia. In a fashion not atypical of a dissent, he identifies and explains what it considers evidentiary fallacies in UT’s compelling interest claim, though in a case involving a plaintiff whose standing remains in question to this day either because of the lack of harm suffered—she graduated from Louisiana State University, or the lack of a valid claim of causation—her indices were too low to get into UT in 2008 when she applied regardless of her race, both largely ignored in the litigation and in Alito’s dissent, complaining about evidentiary fallacies takes a lot of gall. And to Alito, clarity means possibly a quantification of what the University means by critical mass. However, quantification in affirmative action has been verboten since 1978’s Bakke decision where quotas were ruled unconstitutional. In an alternate universe where UT actually makes that argument and supplies the quantification that the Alito in our universe craves, the alternate universe Alito yells “quota” and plays the game of “Gotcha”! So, it seems that Alito would cast the University of Texas in the role of Yossarian, the anti-hero in Joseph Heller’s Catch-22.

In Heller’s classic, Yossarian, a US Army Air Corp pilot, needs a certain number of bombing runs over German held territory to be reassigned during World War II, a standard practice in the Corp to avoid burnout. But as it turns out, the more successful number of sorties run, the more valuable Yossarian and his co-harts became and the promise of reassignment was extended such that it became elusive. Alito dangles the promise of acceptability under the Equal Protection Clause if the University will only provide a number. However, once a number is attached to a critical mass goal, it becomes a quota, and unconstitutional. The Court, before Alito was appointed to the body, understood this and instead of dangling Catch-22 promises, debated the wisdom of affirmative action outright in 2003’s Grutter v. Bollinger. There, the majority understood its limitations as judges, and not educators, and deferred to the educators’ expertise on what critical mass meant in the context of the University of Michigan School of Law.

The Court, by contrast found the same school’s undergraduate program unconstitutional in Gratz v. Bollinger. The Grutter dissents included passionate pleas to overrule the diversity rationale of Bakke, and Justice Thomas quoted Frederick Douglas, no doubt to establish the abolitionist as a traditional opponent of modern day affirmative action (Freedman’s Bureau notwithstanding). The difference between Gratz and Grutter was based on conclusions that the majority in each made in their roles as lawyer/judges. They applied a fairly objective rule, against quotas, and examined whether the programs in the two Michigan programs, amounted to one. As diversity had already been established as a compelling educational interest in Regents of the University of California v. Bakke, the majorities in the two cases did not seek to re-litigate that issue, and instead determined that the law school’s efforts at diversity were not quotas, and the undergraduate admissions program was. No second guessing academic experts in the fashion of Justice Alito 13 years later. Just straight up lawyering by judges, which is what judges are supposed to do, at least according to the standard conservative judicial harangue over the last couple of generations.

What’s at least as troubling is the fact that the Catch-22 is really more than just that—it is a lure into a trap. The opprobrium that would fall on any state school coming close to the banned quota practice would be overwhelming, not to mention the fact that it is an automatic poison pill, as the undergraduate program at the University of Michigan found out in Gratz. Alito’s obsession with scrutinizing decisions of which he has little expertise (higher education), and presumably the obsession of Justice Thomas and Chief Justice Roberts as well, is the open door setting up the trap. The point is that the diversity rationale is rooted in First Amendment jurisprudence protecting academic freedom. As Justice Powell put it in the Bakke decision: "It is the business of a university to provide that atmosphere which is most conducive to speculation, experiment and creation. It is an atmosphere in which there prevail "the four essential freedoms" of a university -- to determine for itself on academic grounds who may teach, what may be taught, how it shall be taught, and who may be admitted to study."

I do not read Powell’s language as giving universities a blank check to administer the Equal Protection Clause independent of judicial scrutiny. In other words, I do not understand the standard to be complete deference. But some deference is required, it would seem, if Powell’s words have any meaning. To require a specific enumeration of the parameters of the school’s interest in this case beyond a critical mass, with reasonable numbers across the board in a variety of courses offered by the University of Texas is to invite the school to a trap. It is a trap decorated with a reasoning that defies Alito’s own aversion to what he calls stereotyping when he suggests that one reason for the lack of minority presence in a number of majors and courses is that there might be courses that are more attractive for minority students than others.

What?

Whether the University of Texas, and the Fifth Circuit, properly responded to the Court’s remand request after the first case, the fact is that a panel of the 5th Circuit, and five Supreme Court justices were satisfied that UT had tightened up its rationale and its description of critical mass satisfactorily.

And Justice Alito and the conservatives who agree with his dissent will continue to ask UT how much diversity is enough diversity-the trap question as if no one will notice.